Reflections on Piaget 1
Running head: REFLECTIONS ON PIAGET
Reflections on Some Work of Jean Piaget
Samuel Otten
Michigan State University
Reflections on Piaget 2
Reflections on Some Work of Jean Piaget
Running head: REFLECTIONS ON PIAGET
Reflections on Some Work of Jean Piaget
Samuel Otten
Michigan State University
Reflections on Piaget 2
Reflections on Some Work of Jean Piaget
Jean Piaget is often called the father of constructivism, and a phrase of his—“To
understand is to discover” (1973, p. 20)1—is often used as the constructivist motto.
Various versions of constructivism (e.g., social, radical) now dominate reform efforts in
education, and they claim to descend (in varying degrees) from Piaget. Even those who
understand is to discover” (1973, p. 20)1—is often used as the constructivist motto.
Various versions of constructivism (e.g., social, radical) now dominate reform efforts in
education, and they claim to descend (in varying degrees) from Piaget. Even those who
attempt to build a philosophy of learning development in contrast to Piaget’s must in
some way deal with his ideas. Thus, it is worthwhile to spend the time and effort behind
this paper delving into some of Piaget’s writing.
Learning and the Stages of Development
It is not insignificant that Piaget wrote that to understand is to discover (see
above), rather than to learn is to discover. (And this word choice is important to
education reformers who follow Piaget because they emphasize teaching for meaning,
or in other words, understanding.) For Piaget, learning can indeed take place without
discovery. He even admits that the stimulus-response model of Watson and Thorndike
accounts for learning—but this type of learning is a particular type and not
characteristic of the broader cognitive picture that Piaget was interested in exploring
and explaining. Before summarizing the stages of development as put forth by Piaget,
then, it is necessary to look more closely at the distinctions he perceived between
learning and development.
Learning and Development
When Piaget used the term “learning” in contrast to the term development (as in
1964), he was referring to specific acquisitions of knowledge that were limited to
1 All references are to Piaget unless otherwise indicated.
Reflections on Piaget 3
particular situations. (This may also be thought of as “learning in the narrow sense.”)
For example, a student has learned something about right triangles when s/he can look
at a side of measure 3 and a side of measure 4 forming a right angle and recall that the
hypotenuse of the triangle has measure 5. This knowledge is specific to the situation
and, Piaget admits, can be taught quite effectively using a behaviorist model of
education.
By “development” of knowledge, Piaget meant the structures of thought that
apply to general situations (1964, p. 7). (This may also be thought of as “learning in the
wider sense.”) With regard to right triangles, a student may have developed a way to
think about them that includes classifications (e.g., right triangles can be isosceles but
not equilateral), general relationships (e.g., the Pythagorean theorem holds), and general
properties (e.g., the right angle is a defining characteristic whereas the hypotenuse being
the longest side is a derived fact). This cognitive structure is developed and is not the
result of specific instruction. How does such development occur?
Contrary to the behaviorists mentioned above, Piaget does not view
development as the “sum of discrete learning experiences” (1964, p. 7). Rather,
development is “the essential process” and particular instances of learning are a
some way deal with his ideas. Thus, it is worthwhile to spend the time and effort behind
this paper delving into some of Piaget’s writing.
Learning and the Stages of Development
It is not insignificant that Piaget wrote that to understand is to discover (see
above), rather than to learn is to discover. (And this word choice is important to
education reformers who follow Piaget because they emphasize teaching for meaning,
or in other words, understanding.) For Piaget, learning can indeed take place without
discovery. He even admits that the stimulus-response model of Watson and Thorndike
accounts for learning—but this type of learning is a particular type and not
characteristic of the broader cognitive picture that Piaget was interested in exploring
and explaining. Before summarizing the stages of development as put forth by Piaget,
then, it is necessary to look more closely at the distinctions he perceived between
learning and development.
Learning and Development
When Piaget used the term “learning” in contrast to the term development (as in
1964), he was referring to specific acquisitions of knowledge that were limited to
1 All references are to Piaget unless otherwise indicated.
Reflections on Piaget 3
particular situations. (This may also be thought of as “learning in the narrow sense.”)
For example, a student has learned something about right triangles when s/he can look
at a side of measure 3 and a side of measure 4 forming a right angle and recall that the
hypotenuse of the triangle has measure 5. This knowledge is specific to the situation
and, Piaget admits, can be taught quite effectively using a behaviorist model of
education.
By “development” of knowledge, Piaget meant the structures of thought that
apply to general situations (1964, p. 7). (This may also be thought of as “learning in the
wider sense.”) With regard to right triangles, a student may have developed a way to
think about them that includes classifications (e.g., right triangles can be isosceles but
not equilateral), general relationships (e.g., the Pythagorean theorem holds), and general
properties (e.g., the right angle is a defining characteristic whereas the hypotenuse being
the longest side is a derived fact). This cognitive structure is developed and is not the
result of specific instruction. How does such development occur?
Contrary to the behaviorists mentioned above, Piaget does not view
development as the “sum of discrete learning experiences” (1964, p. 7). Rather,
development is “the essential process” and particular instances of learning are a
“function of total development.” This notion that “development explains learning” led
Piaget to explore and hypothesize the mechanisms of development—there are four.
First, Piaget noted that maturation—the continuation of embryogenesis—is a
factor in development. The maturation and physical development of an individual,
especially the central nervous system, plays an “indispensable role” (1964, p. 10) in
their cognitive development. This was clear to Piaget and is even clearer now as
Reflections on Piaget 4
neurological research has advanced and shows that certain areas of the brain are related
to certain types of thought which, therefore, cannot advance without the corresponding
brain maturity. Piaget noted, however, that maturation of this sort does not alone
explain cognitive development because there is substantial variation in development
between cultures, even though they are at the same levels of maturation.
Second, Piaget identified experience as a factor in development. Here he was
referring to experience with objects in the physical world. For example, a child’s
various experiences with grasping, pushing, and feeling a wooden block play a role in
the development of a cognitive structure regarding wooden blocks. It should be noted at
this point that Piaget distinguished between two types of experience: physical
experience and logical-mathematical experience. The former refers to experience acting
upon objects and drawing knowledge from those actions. The latter refers to experience
in which the knowledge is gained from the action itself and not the objects involved.
This distinction will resurface below in the discussion of Piaget’s stages of
development. At this point I will just point out that it might have been clearer for Piaget
to make this a distinction, not of experience, but of sources of knowledge from
experience, with physical experience being re-termed an object-source and logicalmathematical
an action-source.
The third factor of development is social transmission. Social transmission
occurs when, for instance, an adult communicates some piece of information to a child.
This factor of development is limited, however, because it is dependent upon the child’s
ability to receive and comprehend the communication.
Reflections on Piaget 5
The fourth factor of development, which Piaget describes as the “fundamental
one” (1964, p. 12), is equilibration. (In a sense, it was misleading for Piaget to list this
on the same level as the other factors of development because equilibration mediates the
others.) Equilibration is the process by which children reconcile their experiences and
their mental schemes (psychological structures that organize experience). This
reconciliation can take the form of assimilation or accommodation (or often both).
Assimilation occurs when experiences (physically with the world or communicatively
with other individuals) are incorporated into existing schemes. For example, imagine a
student who has a scheme for rational numbers characterized by the notion of one
number on top of another number. Now imagine the student coming across -2/5 for the
first time and deciding that it is a rational number. This particular fraction has been
assimilated into the student’s rational number scheme. Accommodation, on the other
hand, occurs when schemes are modified based on experience. An example of this can
be found with another student who has a scheme for rational numbers characterized by
the notion of one positive integer on top of another positive integer. If this student
encounters -2/5 and realizes that it too is a rational number, then the scheme will have
to be modified to accommodate the negative number.
In summary, Piaget contended that the cognitive schemes or structures children
have for organizing their experience develop based on maturation, experience, social
transmission, and above all, equilibration. Experiences are assimilated into existing
schemes and schemes are modified to account for new experiences. This development,
however, does not merely proceed incrementally or quantitatively; there are
Reflections on Piaget 6
qualitatively different stages of cognitive development, and it is to these stages that we
now turn our attention.
The Stages
The sensorimotor stage spans birth until approximately age 2 and is
characterized by the lack of representations for persons or objects; thus interface with
and intelligence about the world are in the form of actions. Initially, infants are unable
to differentiate themselves from their environments and are equipped primarily with
reflexes. Throughout this first stage, the separation between the individual and the rest
of the world is perceived, reflexes become coordinated, causality is recognized, and
means-end sequences are developed. Moreover, the “group of displacements” (Piaget &
Inhelder, 1969, p. 16) is organized and developed by the child and used as a framework
for objects in physical space. The invariant in this group is the existence of the object
itself, and the recognition of this invariant by the child leads to the concept of object
permanence—one of the important accomplishments of the sensorimotor stage.
The preoperational stage spans ages 2 to 7, approximately, and is characterized
by the child’s developing use of symbols (and signs) to represent objects and events in
the world. Although the severe narcissism of infancy has been overcome by this stage,
there still exists an egocentrism of perspective wherein the preoperational child has
difficultly seeing the world from another’s point of view. Furthermore, as illuminated
by many of Piaget’s tasks, children in this stage fail to conserve liquid quantity,
number, and mass. In other words, preoperational children have not yet comprehended
quantity as an invariant in the group of physical transformations (e.g., pouring,
stretching, thinly rolling).
Reflections on Piaget 7
The concrete operational stage spans ages 7 to 11, approximately, and is
characterized by the development of mental operations, as the name suggests. An
operation is an interiorized, generalized, reversible action (1964, p. 7; Piaget &
Inhelder, 1969, p. 96). For example, a child may have had many experiences joining or
combining objects in the world. These physical actions can interiorized as a single,
general mental action. The child can also come to understand that joining is undone by
separating and in so doing acquire an operation that we might call “addition.”
Operations such as addition can be powerfully used by concrete operational children to
solve problems and reason about the world. Our child above, for instance, can solve
addition problems without needing to rely on physical models of the situations in
questions. Thinking in this stage is still limited, however, as children have difficulty
thinking in hypothetical terms or outside of the “here and now.”
The formal operational stage spans approximately age 11 through adulthood
and is characterized by abstract thought and deductive reasoning. Formal thinkers are
able to apply their mental operations to abstract entities in hypothetical situations. In
mathematics, for example, a student in the formal operational stage would be able to
successfully consider and work within spaces different than familiar Euclidean space.
Thus far, I have briefly laid forth Piaget’s notions of learning and development,
the mechanisms he identified as underlying development, and the stages through which
he hypothesized children’s thinking progresses. What does this theory contribute to
issues of teaching and learning? It is to this matter that I now turn.
Piaget and the Classroom
Reflections on Piaget 8
As a teacher of mathematics, I can identify several ways in which Piaget’s
theory of cognitive development can influence (and hopefully improve) classroom
practice, the first of which comes from the initial distinction between learning and
development. It is important to keep in mind that discrete pieces of narrow learning do
not necessarily lead to development on the part of the student. I have seen this failed
implication many times in mathematics classrooms where some students cling to a vast
array of allowable algebraic manipulations but have not developed an adequate scheme
of equality, and in university mathematics tutoring centers where some students
mindlessly apply rules of differentiation with no understanding of what these rules
produce or why they work. In both of these cases, it is clear to me that the students have
learned in the narrow sense but not the wider sense.
Piaget’s theory not only provides a language for describing such problems in
mathematics learning, but also supplies tools with which to avoid them. One that seems
especially important to me is based on the notion of equilibration. As mathematical
concepts are introduced and encountered in the classroom (note that I am assuming
mathematics classrooms are a place in which mathematical concepts are actually
encountered), students formulate (or refine) schemes with which they organize these
encounters. As new experiences arise concerning a particular concept, these experiences
are either assimilated to the existing schemes or the schemes are modified to
accommodate the experience. A teacher who is mindful of these possibilities may be
able to better guide the experiences in a way that results in a sophisticated and robust
scheme.
Reflections on Piaget 9
This paper began with a quote from Piaget that, on the face of it, seemed to be
steeped in classroom implications. The full passage is this: “To understand is to
discover, or reconstruct by rediscovery, and such conditions must be complied with if in
the future individuals are to be formed who are capable of production and creativity and
not simply repetition” (1973, p. 20). However, the term “discover” did not appear even
once in the treatment above of the factors and stages of development. What, then, did
Piaget mean by “discover”? I posit that discovery has two facets; using the language of
Piaget’s theory of development, I say that discovery consists of active (on the part of the
student) arrival at a state of disequilibrium and active (on the part of the student)
equilibration. This definition does not mean that the arrival at disequilibrium or the
equilibration has to be a solitary act—cooperative action can still result in discovery—
but it does preclude a student being led directly to or directly through disequilibrium.
Now, this interpretation of discovery seems to point to the importance of having
students actively engage their existing schemes with new experiences in the classroom,
designing lessons in which disequilibrium can be arrived at, and cultivating
environments in which equilibration can be achieved, resulting in modified cognitive
structures. Piaget said that that learning of this sort results in understanding. He also
seems to have said that understanding only arises through discovery (though the logic of
his quotation is not clear due to the particular phrasing). One may debate this by saying
that a state of disequilibrium or the process of equilibration can be prompted through
social transmission—that is, a non-discovery process—and understanding can result
from this disequilibrium and equilibration regardless of what led to it. While this is true,
the point is subtle because equilibration does not take place, by definition, until the
Reflections on Piaget 10
student actively engages in it—so it may be the case that the student did not discover
the entirety of the phenomena, but understanding depends upon the student picking up
the reigns of discovery at some point.
As an example of this subtle issue, consider three situations concerning the
classification relationship between rectangles and squares. In the first case, the teacher
leads a student through considerations of different quadrilaterals and then asks whether
or not the squares are rectangles. After a moment, the teacher declares that squares are
rectangles because they have four right angles. In this case, it is possible that the student
was not listening and so does not understand the relationship between squares and
rectangles; it is also possible that the student was listening and memorized the teacher’s
final explanation but does not truly understand the relationship. It is possible that the
student was engaged in a mental process of discovery along with the teacher, but it is
also possible that this did not happen. In the second case, the teacher and a student
consider different quadrilaterals and then the teacher asks if squares can also be
rectangles. The student is perplexed by this question but using the shapes available and
the guidance of the teacher is able to become convinced that all squares must also be
rectangles. In this case, the student did not discover the situation of disequilibrium but
was led to it by the teacher. The student did, however, discover the resolution to the
situation and so likely understands the relationship in question. In the third case, a
student works independently classifying quadrilaterals and realizes that she doesn’t
know whether to put the squares with the rectangles or in their own separate pile. She
considers this problem and, using her knowledge of squares and rectangles, correctly
modifies her scheme for rectangles to include squares. In this case, the student
Reflections on Piaget 11
discovered the disequilibrium and its resolution so we can be confident that she
understands the classification relationship between squares and rectangles.
Whether or not Piaget is justified in his use of the term “discover” (that is, based
on the examples above, he may simply mean that to understand is to actively work to
equilibration), the broader point is that understanding is tied to students’ actively
working to make sense of their experiences and to integrate their discrete, “narrow”
pieces of knowledge. This sense-making process, comprising assimilation and
accommodation, is essentially a path of discovery for every individual student.
Reflections on Piaget 12
References
Ginsburg, H. P., & Opper, S. (1969). Biography and basic ideas. In Piaget's theory of intellectual
development (pp. 1-25). Englewood Cliffs, NJ: Prentice Hall.
Piaget, J. (1964). Development and learning. In R. Ripple & V. Rockcastle (Eds.), Piaget
rediscovered (pp. 7-19). Ithaca, NY: Cornell University.
Piaget, J. (1973). To understand is to invent: The future of education (G. A. Roberts, Trans.).
New York: Grossman Publishers.
Piaget, J., & Inhelder, B. (1969). The psychology of the child (H. Weaver, Trans.). New York:
Basic Books, Inc.
Piaget to explore and hypothesize the mechanisms of development—there are four.
First, Piaget noted that maturation—the continuation of embryogenesis—is a
factor in development. The maturation and physical development of an individual,
especially the central nervous system, plays an “indispensable role” (1964, p. 10) in
their cognitive development. This was clear to Piaget and is even clearer now as
Reflections on Piaget 4
neurological research has advanced and shows that certain areas of the brain are related
to certain types of thought which, therefore, cannot advance without the corresponding
brain maturity. Piaget noted, however, that maturation of this sort does not alone
explain cognitive development because there is substantial variation in development
between cultures, even though they are at the same levels of maturation.
Second, Piaget identified experience as a factor in development. Here he was
referring to experience with objects in the physical world. For example, a child’s
various experiences with grasping, pushing, and feeling a wooden block play a role in
the development of a cognitive structure regarding wooden blocks. It should be noted at
this point that Piaget distinguished between two types of experience: physical
experience and logical-mathematical experience. The former refers to experience acting
upon objects and drawing knowledge from those actions. The latter refers to experience
in which the knowledge is gained from the action itself and not the objects involved.
This distinction will resurface below in the discussion of Piaget’s stages of
development. At this point I will just point out that it might have been clearer for Piaget
to make this a distinction, not of experience, but of sources of knowledge from
experience, with physical experience being re-termed an object-source and logicalmathematical
an action-source.
The third factor of development is social transmission. Social transmission
occurs when, for instance, an adult communicates some piece of information to a child.
This factor of development is limited, however, because it is dependent upon the child’s
ability to receive and comprehend the communication.
Reflections on Piaget 5
The fourth factor of development, which Piaget describes as the “fundamental
one” (1964, p. 12), is equilibration. (In a sense, it was misleading for Piaget to list this
on the same level as the other factors of development because equilibration mediates the
others.) Equilibration is the process by which children reconcile their experiences and
their mental schemes (psychological structures that organize experience). This
reconciliation can take the form of assimilation or accommodation (or often both).
Assimilation occurs when experiences (physically with the world or communicatively
with other individuals) are incorporated into existing schemes. For example, imagine a
student who has a scheme for rational numbers characterized by the notion of one
number on top of another number. Now imagine the student coming across -2/5 for the
first time and deciding that it is a rational number. This particular fraction has been
assimilated into the student’s rational number scheme. Accommodation, on the other
hand, occurs when schemes are modified based on experience. An example of this can
be found with another student who has a scheme for rational numbers characterized by
the notion of one positive integer on top of another positive integer. If this student
encounters -2/5 and realizes that it too is a rational number, then the scheme will have
to be modified to accommodate the negative number.
In summary, Piaget contended that the cognitive schemes or structures children
have for organizing their experience develop based on maturation, experience, social
transmission, and above all, equilibration. Experiences are assimilated into existing
schemes and schemes are modified to account for new experiences. This development,
however, does not merely proceed incrementally or quantitatively; there are
Reflections on Piaget 6
qualitatively different stages of cognitive development, and it is to these stages that we
now turn our attention.
The Stages
The sensorimotor stage spans birth until approximately age 2 and is
characterized by the lack of representations for persons or objects; thus interface with
and intelligence about the world are in the form of actions. Initially, infants are unable
to differentiate themselves from their environments and are equipped primarily with
reflexes. Throughout this first stage, the separation between the individual and the rest
of the world is perceived, reflexes become coordinated, causality is recognized, and
means-end sequences are developed. Moreover, the “group of displacements” (Piaget &
Inhelder, 1969, p. 16) is organized and developed by the child and used as a framework
for objects in physical space. The invariant in this group is the existence of the object
itself, and the recognition of this invariant by the child leads to the concept of object
permanence—one of the important accomplishments of the sensorimotor stage.
The preoperational stage spans ages 2 to 7, approximately, and is characterized
by the child’s developing use of symbols (and signs) to represent objects and events in
the world. Although the severe narcissism of infancy has been overcome by this stage,
there still exists an egocentrism of perspective wherein the preoperational child has
difficultly seeing the world from another’s point of view. Furthermore, as illuminated
by many of Piaget’s tasks, children in this stage fail to conserve liquid quantity,
number, and mass. In other words, preoperational children have not yet comprehended
quantity as an invariant in the group of physical transformations (e.g., pouring,
stretching, thinly rolling).
Reflections on Piaget 7
The concrete operational stage spans ages 7 to 11, approximately, and is
characterized by the development of mental operations, as the name suggests. An
operation is an interiorized, generalized, reversible action (1964, p. 7; Piaget &
Inhelder, 1969, p. 96). For example, a child may have had many experiences joining or
combining objects in the world. These physical actions can interiorized as a single,
general mental action. The child can also come to understand that joining is undone by
separating and in so doing acquire an operation that we might call “addition.”
Operations such as addition can be powerfully used by concrete operational children to
solve problems and reason about the world. Our child above, for instance, can solve
addition problems without needing to rely on physical models of the situations in
questions. Thinking in this stage is still limited, however, as children have difficulty
thinking in hypothetical terms or outside of the “here and now.”
The formal operational stage spans approximately age 11 through adulthood
and is characterized by abstract thought and deductive reasoning. Formal thinkers are
able to apply their mental operations to abstract entities in hypothetical situations. In
mathematics, for example, a student in the formal operational stage would be able to
successfully consider and work within spaces different than familiar Euclidean space.
Thus far, I have briefly laid forth Piaget’s notions of learning and development,
the mechanisms he identified as underlying development, and the stages through which
he hypothesized children’s thinking progresses. What does this theory contribute to
issues of teaching and learning? It is to this matter that I now turn.
Piaget and the Classroom
Reflections on Piaget 8
As a teacher of mathematics, I can identify several ways in which Piaget’s
theory of cognitive development can influence (and hopefully improve) classroom
practice, the first of which comes from the initial distinction between learning and
development. It is important to keep in mind that discrete pieces of narrow learning do
not necessarily lead to development on the part of the student. I have seen this failed
implication many times in mathematics classrooms where some students cling to a vast
array of allowable algebraic manipulations but have not developed an adequate scheme
of equality, and in university mathematics tutoring centers where some students
mindlessly apply rules of differentiation with no understanding of what these rules
produce or why they work. In both of these cases, it is clear to me that the students have
learned in the narrow sense but not the wider sense.
Piaget’s theory not only provides a language for describing such problems in
mathematics learning, but also supplies tools with which to avoid them. One that seems
especially important to me is based on the notion of equilibration. As mathematical
concepts are introduced and encountered in the classroom (note that I am assuming
mathematics classrooms are a place in which mathematical concepts are actually
encountered), students formulate (or refine) schemes with which they organize these
encounters. As new experiences arise concerning a particular concept, these experiences
are either assimilated to the existing schemes or the schemes are modified to
accommodate the experience. A teacher who is mindful of these possibilities may be
able to better guide the experiences in a way that results in a sophisticated and robust
scheme.
Reflections on Piaget 9
This paper began with a quote from Piaget that, on the face of it, seemed to be
steeped in classroom implications. The full passage is this: “To understand is to
discover, or reconstruct by rediscovery, and such conditions must be complied with if in
the future individuals are to be formed who are capable of production and creativity and
not simply repetition” (1973, p. 20). However, the term “discover” did not appear even
once in the treatment above of the factors and stages of development. What, then, did
Piaget mean by “discover”? I posit that discovery has two facets; using the language of
Piaget’s theory of development, I say that discovery consists of active (on the part of the
student) arrival at a state of disequilibrium and active (on the part of the student)
equilibration. This definition does not mean that the arrival at disequilibrium or the
equilibration has to be a solitary act—cooperative action can still result in discovery—
but it does preclude a student being led directly to or directly through disequilibrium.
Now, this interpretation of discovery seems to point to the importance of having
students actively engage their existing schemes with new experiences in the classroom,
designing lessons in which disequilibrium can be arrived at, and cultivating
environments in which equilibration can be achieved, resulting in modified cognitive
structures. Piaget said that that learning of this sort results in understanding. He also
seems to have said that understanding only arises through discovery (though the logic of
his quotation is not clear due to the particular phrasing). One may debate this by saying
that a state of disequilibrium or the process of equilibration can be prompted through
social transmission—that is, a non-discovery process—and understanding can result
from this disequilibrium and equilibration regardless of what led to it. While this is true,
the point is subtle because equilibration does not take place, by definition, until the
Reflections on Piaget 10
student actively engages in it—so it may be the case that the student did not discover
the entirety of the phenomena, but understanding depends upon the student picking up
the reigns of discovery at some point.
As an example of this subtle issue, consider three situations concerning the
classification relationship between rectangles and squares. In the first case, the teacher
leads a student through considerations of different quadrilaterals and then asks whether
or not the squares are rectangles. After a moment, the teacher declares that squares are
rectangles because they have four right angles. In this case, it is possible that the student
was not listening and so does not understand the relationship between squares and
rectangles; it is also possible that the student was listening and memorized the teacher’s
final explanation but does not truly understand the relationship. It is possible that the
student was engaged in a mental process of discovery along with the teacher, but it is
also possible that this did not happen. In the second case, the teacher and a student
consider different quadrilaterals and then the teacher asks if squares can also be
rectangles. The student is perplexed by this question but using the shapes available and
the guidance of the teacher is able to become convinced that all squares must also be
rectangles. In this case, the student did not discover the situation of disequilibrium but
was led to it by the teacher. The student did, however, discover the resolution to the
situation and so likely understands the relationship in question. In the third case, a
student works independently classifying quadrilaterals and realizes that she doesn’t
know whether to put the squares with the rectangles or in their own separate pile. She
considers this problem and, using her knowledge of squares and rectangles, correctly
modifies her scheme for rectangles to include squares. In this case, the student
Reflections on Piaget 11
discovered the disequilibrium and its resolution so we can be confident that she
understands the classification relationship between squares and rectangles.
Whether or not Piaget is justified in his use of the term “discover” (that is, based
on the examples above, he may simply mean that to understand is to actively work to
equilibration), the broader point is that understanding is tied to students’ actively
working to make sense of their experiences and to integrate their discrete, “narrow”
pieces of knowledge. This sense-making process, comprising assimilation and
accommodation, is essentially a path of discovery for every individual student.
Reflections on Piaget 12
References
Ginsburg, H. P., & Opper, S. (1969). Biography and basic ideas. In Piaget's theory of intellectual
development (pp. 1-25). Englewood Cliffs, NJ: Prentice Hall.
Piaget, J. (1964). Development and learning. In R. Ripple & V. Rockcastle (Eds.), Piaget
rediscovered (pp. 7-19). Ithaca, NY: Cornell University.
Piaget, J. (1973). To understand is to invent: The future of education (G. A. Roberts, Trans.).
New York: Grossman Publishers.
Piaget, J., & Inhelder, B. (1969). The psychology of the child (H. Weaver, Trans.). New York:
Basic Books, Inc.
No comments:
Post a Comment